Modal logic 1.4 - truth trees for invalid arguments in K

แชร์
ฝัง
  • เผยแพร่เมื่อ 31 ม.ค. 2013
  • I use truth trees to show the invalidity of two arguments in K, and I explain how truth trees provide an easy method for finding counterexamples to invalid arguments.

ความคิดเห็น • 14

  • @JonSebastianF
    @JonSebastianF 3 ปีที่แล้ว +4

    3:50 explained:
    A 'trick' is: Moving the ~ through the operators, □ or ◇, flips their respective values around, so that ~□p flips to ◇~p, and ~◇p flips to □~p.
    Using this trick here on “~□◇p” leaves you two options: Moving the ~ once or twice:
    · Moving it once, gives ◇~◇p, from which we derive “~◇p” in w2.
    · Moving it twice, gives ◇□~p, from which we derive “□~p” in w2.

  • @Aglaophamus1
    @Aglaophamus1 8 ปีที่แล้ว +2

    1:15 I think you mean the fallacy of affirming the consequent. Thanks for making these videos!

  • @JonSebastianF
    @JonSebastianF 3 ปีที่แล้ว +1

    5:54 _“(...) If neither the variable, nor its negation, occurs, then we put the negation in the corresponding world.”_ ...Why is this so? Why does that imply the negation?

  • @bertrandrussell6470
    @bertrandrussell6470 10 ปีที่แล้ว +2

    Forgive me if you already explained this in another video, but why is it that you write ~p in the counterexample when neither p nor ~p occurs in the corresponding world?

    • @orangereplyer
      @orangereplyer 4 ปีที่แล้ว

      He could've chosen to put p instead; either choice would've worked.

  • @Alkis05
    @Alkis05 3 ปีที่แล้ว

    9:50 The other counter example would be the same, but with Valuation(w3,~p & q)

  • @ktube2482
    @ktube2482 7 ปีที่แล้ว +1

    Why can you infer ~diamond(p) from ~box,diamond(p)? Please if someone sees this, help me out.

    • @physics_philosophy_faith
      @physics_philosophy_faith 3 ปีที่แล้ว +1

      This took me a minute too. ~necessary(x) is identical to possibly(~x). This means you open up a new world with ~x in it. Here, x = diamond(p). So the new world should have ~diamond(p).

    • @JonSebastianF
      @JonSebastianF 3 ปีที่แล้ว

      A 'trick' is: Moving the ~ through the operators, □ or ◇, flips their respective values around, so that ~□p flips to ◇~p, and ~◇p flips to □~p.
      Using this trick here on “~□◇p” leaves you two options: Moving the ~ once or twice:
      · Moving it once, gives ◇~◇p, from which we derive “~◇p” in w2.
      · Moving it twice, gives ◇□~p, from which we derive “□~p” in w2.

  • @KaneB
    @KaneB  11 ปีที่แล้ว +3

    If ~[]p is true, then, obviously, []p is false. And *any* material conditional with a false antecedent is true. So since []p is false, []p -> []q is true.

  • @turnz153
    @turnz153 8 หลายเดือนก่อน

    5:25

  • @wenaolong
    @wenaolong 7 ปีที่แล้ว

    I think it should be said that in w2, it is possibly not possibly p, or possibly necessarily not p. And so that means there is at least one possible world where it is necessarily true that not-p. Therefore it is necessarily true in all possible worlds that it is possibly true in some world, in this case w2, that necessarily not-p, and so it is necessarily not-p in all possible worlds.
    But in w1 p is true. So by "revival", we can import not-p back to w1, and have a contradiction. This appeals to the intuition that if it is possibly true, then it is true in all possible worlds that it is possibly true, and so it is necessarily true that it is possibly true. Ah, but I suppose that K is very different from S5, and I am thinking in S5... K is quite weird. Accessibility becomes a key issue in order to make it "reasonable" for our use in any practical way it seems.

    • @physics_philosophy_faith
      @physics_philosophy_faith 3 ปีที่แล้ว

      "possibly not possibly p" would only belong in w0, not w2. The "possibly" is removed because you are opening up a new world, w2, and then putting "not possibly p" there. That is how we have been defining and using "possibly(p)" by opening up a new world and putting p in it, not putting possibly(p) in the new world